Document Type : Research Paper

Author

.

Abstract

In this paper an economic-philosophical explanation concerning the status of egoism and justice-seeking is presented in consumer theory, which can be considered formally as an axiomatic theory and in nature as a strong version of rational choice theory. By analyzing the structure of an axiomatic theory in general and consumer theory in particular, and proposing the hypothesis that there exists an egoistic value base in this theory, and in order to confirm this hypothesis, an emphasis is given to the necessity of a theoretical framework for the definition of egoism and justice-seeking terms. The definitions of these two terms are then explained according to Rawlsian theory of justice in order to provide a background for presenting two basic questions as follows: Firstly, should human being as a consumer and more generally as a decision maker select either egoism or justice-seeking? Secondly, if so, how this selection is being made? In answering these questions, it is argued that by applying rational choice theory and Rawlsian theory of justice simultaneously, consumer ̓s preferences are reducible to two basic desires of egoism and justice-seeking. Lastly, it is concluded by comparison between Rawls’ and Hobbes’ views that philosophical anthropology as a fundamental component of this philosophical system is a determinant factor in selecting either egoism or justice-seeking in various areas including in consumer theory.
 

Keywords

افلاطون (1353)، جمهور، مترجم محمدحسن لطفی، چاپ اول، تهران: ابن‌سینا.
سروش، عبدالکریم (1368)، علم چیست؟ فلسفه چیست؟، چاپ دهم، تهران: موسسه فرهنگی صراط.
مشهدی‌احمد، محمود (1394)، «نهادگرایی قدیم و اقتصاد مرسوم؛ یک جدال فکری»، فصلنامه پژوهشنامه اقتصادی، سال پانزدهم، شماره57، صص1-38.
هابز، توماس (1380)، لویاتان، مترجم حسین بشیریه، تهران: نشر نی.
 
Becker, Gary S.; Stigler and J. George  (March 1977),“De Gustibus non est Disputandum”,The American Economic Review. American Economic Association. 67 (2): 76–90.
Blume, E. and D. Easley (2008),“Rationality”, The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics , 2nd Edition.
Debreu, G. (1959), Theory of Value: An Axiomatic Analysis of Economic Equilibriu,. New York: Wiley.
Dietrich, F. and C. List, (2013), “Where do Preferences Come from?” Int Game Theory, 42: 613. doi:10.1007/s00182-012-0333-y
Hobbes, T., 1651, Leviathan, in E. Curley (ed.), Leviathan, with selected variants from the Latin edition of 1668, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1994.
Hansson, Sven Ove and Grüne-Yanoff, Till, Preferences, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/preferences/>.
Jehle. G. A. and J. Reny, P. J. (2011), Advanced Microeconomic Theory, Third edition.
Wayne P. Pomerleau,“Justice, Western Theories of”, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. www.iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 2016-03-02.
Mas-Colell, A. , M.D. Whinston, and  J.R. Green (1995), Microeconomic Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pogge, T.,2002, World Poverty and Human Rights, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Popper, K.,(1945), “The Open Society and Its Enemies”, 2 volumes. London: Routledge.
Rawls. John. (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge: Belnap Press of the Harvard University Press.
Rawls, J., (1999), The Law of Peoples, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Robbins, L. (1935), “An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science”, 2nd edn. London: Macmillan.
Sen. Amartya K. (1976), “Real National Income”, Review of Economic Studies, 43, no. 1: 19-39.
Suppes, P. (1987), Axiomatic Theories, The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, First Edition, Edited by John Eatwell, Murray Milgate and Peter.